In 1864,
William Tecumseh Sherman, a Union General during the US Civil War, began what
became known as the ‘March to the Sea,’ a scorched-earth military campaign through
enemy territory. The campaign covered five weeks, during which time Sherman
destroyed civilian industrial capacity, infrastructure and most civilian
property he crossed. His troops burnt crops and killed livestock.
That March was
controversial. But its brutality is said by some to have contributed to the end
of that war.
Was
Sherman’s March morally correct?
General
Sherman is credited with coining the expression, ‘War is Hell.’ But today, war
is more than ‘Hell;’ it is also an
ethicist’s laboratory.
In the Middle
East Arab-Israel conflict war is also an ethical battlefield, where morality
becomes a political weapon for those who are cruel and immoral.
Man tries to
make war ethical. Ethics in war seems counter-intuitive, but because war is so
horrific, establishing rules of behaviour can in theory benefit both sides. The
ethical challenge is, how to create rules that both sides accept.
Ethicists
have learned that rules can work—for the most part—when you see your enemy as human--one
with whom you share a moral identity--and with whom you know you will do
business after war is over.
But when you
see your enemy as less than human, war conventions are rarely applied (see “Just
war theory [the Internet Encyclopaedia of Philosophy],” Alexander Moseley, Iep.utm.edu, 2009-02-10).
This is the
problem with the Arab-Israel conflict. Arabs see Jews as less-than-human. Arab
media, politicians and clergy publically dehumanize Jews. If the United Nations argues
that such attitudes do not remove ethical responsibility from Israel, others
can make the case that Arab behaviour in war—founded on the dehumanization of
its enemy—actually changes the rules of war; for, as stated above, rules of war
rarely apply when dehumanization of an enemy occurs.
Should dehumanization
play a role in determining human rights enforcement during war? Or, if those
who dehumanize their enemy refuse to act morally in a war against that enemy, what
human rights protections do they deserve?
Many ethicists--and virtually all human rights advocates--reject the dehumanization
question to take an absolute stand: even as one side breaks the rules (and uses
human shields, for example), the other side is still morally obligated to obey
the rules.
Is that
moral?
Absolute
standards in such a situation do not promote moral behaviour in war (ibid); instead,
they create a foundation for political rather than moral interests.
Is it moral
for morality to be managed by political agendas?
Applying an
inflexible moral standard to a war where only one side accepts that standard
could be immoral. Discussions of moral behaviour in war depend upon the
question of what is ‘just’. Giving one side in conflict an unjust advantage breaches the ethicists’ commitment to that sense
of ‘just-ness’.
We must determine
who is morally responsible for protecting civilians. But we must not do that to the disadvantage of
the side that upholds the rules.
That would
not be moral. It would not be ‘just’.
The UN,
however, appears to work with a rigid moral standard for war rules, even in
cases where one side refuses to accept that standard. Common sense suggests
that if one side rejects all conventions and uses human shields and civilian
casualties to promote its success at the expense of the enemy, the moral
responsibility should lie with that side—because, for one thing, it is they who
control those civilians.
In war, you
should be morally responsible for what you control—not for what your enemy
controls.
According to
the accepted rules of war, Israel has a just cause for its 2012 attack against
Gaza—self defense. But if Israel obeys the rules and refrains always from
harming illegally placed human shields, avoids military targets because they
have been deliberately established within civilian population centers and insists
that it will kill only those who wear identifiable military uniforms, then
Israel cannot win that war; she could hardly fire a shot for fear of killing civilians.
Worse for Israel,
modern ethical rules are so exact that they deny a war’s morality if there is
no chance for a beneficial outcome. If Israel initiates a war it cannot
prosecute, it starts a war that does not have a potentially beneficial outcome;
therefore, it could be starting an immoral war.
Rules that
have been designed to mollify the horrors of war now prevent Israel from
protecting her citizens which, according to those same rules, is a legitimate
cause for war.
It’s an
impossible moral catch-22. Israel loses if she doesn’t fight and she loses if
she does fight.
Ethicists have
created a monster. They intend to empower morality in war. But they create the opposite effect: they empower
the cruel and the immoral by denying a sovereign power the right to defend itself.
No comments:
Post a Comment